Moral Pluralism: Beyond Harm
A pluralist theory is one which entails that there are multiple kinds
of moral concern which are not reducible to just one ultimate concern; for example, both purity and harm.
By contrast, a monist theory is one which identifies one fundamental aspect, most likely harm,
or something related to harm, as the sole basis for all genuinely moral concern.
What kind of evidence might favour descriptive moral pluralism over monism? This section introduces two key sources.
Notes
In order to describe human moral psychology, do we need to recognise
incommensurable kinds of moral concern?
This section offers three reasons for a positive answer.
First, it seems that harm- and purity-related concerns are incommensurable; and both
kinds of concern appear to be involved in ordinary moral judgements
(Chakroff, Dungan, & Young, 2013; Chakroff, Russell, Piazza, & Young, 2017).
Second,specific kinds of moral concern (e.g. purity) appear to have had different roles in evolution.
For instance, van Leeuwen, Park, Koenig, & Graham (2012) had subjects answer questions which
indicated the degree to which they endorsed moral concerns linked to purity, authority and loyalty
(the ‘binding foundations’) compared to the degree to which they endorsed moral
foundations linked to harm and unfairness (the ‘individual foundations’).
They found a link between stronger endorsement of binding foundations and
the historical prevalence of pathogens in the region subjects lived:
‘historical pathogen prevalence—even when controlling for individual-level
variation in political orientation, gender, education, and
age—significantly predicted endorsement of Ingroup/loyalty [stats removed], Authority/respect,
and Purity/sanctity; it did not predict
endorsement of Harm/care or Fairness/reciprocity’
(van Leeuwen et al., 2012).
This is coherent with the idea that purity has been important because it enabled
humans to mitigate risks from pathogens associated with their diet long before they understood
pathogens.
The third reason for accepting (descriptive) moral pluralism is that it appears to be
needed to explain how cultural differences in moral psychology underpin attitudes to homosexuality.
Greater endorsement of binding foundations appears to
explain stronger homophobia (Koleva, Graham, Iyer, Ditto, & Haidt, 2012), and this may explain why both
being more socially conservative (Barnett, Öz, & Marsden, 2018)
and being more sensitive to disgust (Lai, Haidt, & Nosek, 2014) is correlated with being more homophobic.
While none of these reasons are decisive, it appears that moral pluralism is needed for a variety
of explanations. This justifies us in accepting that there are several kinds of moral concern.
Descriptive vs Normative Moral Pluralism
Our focus on this course is humans’ ethical abilities. We are therefore interested in whether
or not we need to recognize that they invovle multiple moral concerns that cannot be
reduced to one ultimate concern. This is a concern about descriptive moral pluralism.
There is a distinct, narrowly philosophical question: Are ‘different values [...] all
reducible to one supervalue, or [... are] there really are several distinct values’ (Mason, 2018)?
This is a question about normative moral pluralism.
Given that humans’ ethical abilities are limited and may not reflect how things actually are,
one might be a descriptive moral pluralism but a normative monist (or conversely).
Ask a Question
Your question will normally be answered in the question
session of the next lecture.
More information about asking questions.
Glossary
binding foundations :
Categories of moral concern linked to social needs; these are often taken to be
betrayal/loyalty, subversion/authority, and impurity/purity (Graham et al., 2011).
individual foundations :
Categories of moral concern linked to individual needs; these are often taken to be
harm/care, cheating/fairness (Graham et al., 2011). Sometimes called individualizing foundations.
moral disengagement :
Moral disengagement occurs when self-sanctions are disengaged from
conduct. To illustrate, an executioner may avoid self-sanctioning for killing
by reframing the role they play as ‘babysitting’ (Bandura, 2002, p. 103).
Bandura (2002, p. 111) identifies several
mechanisms of moral disengagement: ‘The disengagement may centre on
redefining harmful conduct as honourable by moral justification, exonerating
social comparison and sanitising language. It may focus on agency of action
so that perpetrators can minimise their role in causing harm by diffusion
and displacement of responsibility. It may involve minimising or distorting
the harm that follows from detrimental actions; and the disengagement may
include dehumanising and blaming the victims of the maltreatment.’
moral pluralism :
Descriptive moral pluralism is the view that humans’ ethical abilities involve distinct moral concerns (such as harm, equality and purity) which are not reducible to just one moral concern.
References
Atari, M., Haidt, J., Graham, J., Koleva, S., Stevens, S. T., & Dehghani, M. (2023). Morality beyond the WEIRD: How the nomological network of morality varies across cultures.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
125(5), 1157–1188.
https://doi.org/10.1037/pspp0000470
Bandura, A. (2002). Selective Moral Disengagement in the Exercise of Moral Agency.
Journal of Moral Education,
31(2), 101–119.
https://doi.org/10.1080/0305724022014322
Barnett, M. D., Öz, H. C. M., & Marsden, A. D. (2018). Economic and Social Political Ideology and Homophobia: The Mediating Role of Binding and Individualizing Moral Foundations.
Archives of Sexual Behavior,
47(4), 1183–1194.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10508-017-0989-2
Chakroff, A., Dungan, J., & Young, L. (2013). Harming Ourselves and Defiling Others: What Determines a Moral Domain?
PLOS ONE,
8(9), e74434.
https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0074434
Chakroff, A., Russell, P. S., Piazza, J., & Young, L. (2017). From impure to harmful: Asymmetric expectations about immoral agents.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
69, 201–209.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jesp.2016.08.001
Crone, D. L., & Laham, S. M. (2015). Multiple moral foundations predict responses to sacrificial dilemmas.
Personality and Individual Differences,
85, 60–65.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.paid.2015.04.041
Dungan, J. A., Chakroff, A., & Young, L. (2017). The relevance of moral norms in distinct relational contexts: Purity versus harm norms regulate self-directed actions.
PLOS ONE,
12(3), e0173405.
https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0173405
Feinberg, M., & Willer, R. (2013). The Moral Roots of Environmental Attitudes.
Psychological Science,
24(1), 56–62.
https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797612449177
Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., Iyer, R., Wojcik, S. P., & Ditto, P. H. (2013). Moral Foundations Theory: The Pragmatic Validity of Moral Pluralism. In P. Devine & A. Plant (Eds.),
Advances in Experimental Social Psychology (Vol. 47, pp. 55–130). Academic Press.
https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-12-407236-7.00002-4
Graham, J., Haidt, J., Motyl, M., Meindl, P., Iskiwitch, C., & Mooijman, M. (2019). Moral Foundations Theory: On the advantages of moral pluralism over moral monism. In K. Gray & J. Graham (Eds.),
Atlas of Moral Psychology. New York: Guilford Publications.
Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. (2009). Liberals and conservatives rely on different sets of moral foundations.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
96(5), 1029–1046.
https://doi.org/10.1037/a0015141
Graham, J., Nosek, B. A., Haidt, J., Iyer, R., Koleva, S., & Ditto, P. H. (2011). Mapping the moral domain.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
101(2), 366–385.
https://doi.org/10.1037/a0021847
Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics: How innately prepared intuitions generate culturally variable virtues.
Daedalus,
133(4), 55–66.
https://doi.org/10.1162/0011526042365555
Hendel, R. S. (1987). Of Demigods and the Deluge: Toward an Interpretation of Genesis 6:1-4.
Journal of Biblical Literature,
106(1), 13–26.
https://doi.org/10.2307/3260551
Koleva, S. P., Graham, J., Iyer, R., Ditto, P. H., & Haidt, J. (2012). Tracing the threads: How five moral concerns (especially Purity) help explain culture war attitudes.
Journal of Research in Personality,
46(2), 184–194.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jrp.2012.01.006
Lai, C. K., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. (2014). Moral elevation reduces prejudice against gay men.
Cognition and Emotion,
28(5), 781–794.
https://doi.org/10.1080/02699931.2013.861342
Mason, E. (2018). Value Pluralism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.),
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved from
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/value-pluralism/
Perry, G. H., Dominy, N. J., Claw, K. G., Lee, A. S., Fiegler, H., Redon, R., … Stone, A. C. (2007). Diet and the evolution of human amylase gene copy number variation.
Nature Genetics,
39(10), 1256–1260.
https://doi.org/10.1038/ng2123
Roberts, P., & Stewart, B. A. (2018). Defining the ‘generalist specialist’ niche for Pleistocene Homo sapiens.
Nature Human Behaviour,
2(8), 542–550.
https://doi.org/10.1038/s41562-018-0394-4
van Leeuwen, F., Park, J. H., Koenig, B. L., & Graham, J. (2012). Regional variation in pathogen prevalence predicts endorsement of group-focused moral concerns.
Evolution and Human Behavior,
33(5), 429–437.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2011.12.005