Link Search Menu Expand Document

Moral Intuitions

A person’s intuitions are the claims they take to be true independently of whether those claims are justified inferentially. And a person’s moral intuitions are those of their intuitions that concern ethical matters. Moral intuitions matter philosophically because they are widely held to be necessary, one way or another, for ethical knowledge. They also matter scientifically insofar as they underpin abilities to produce fast ethical responses.

This recording is also available on stream (no ads; search enabled). Or you can view just the slides (no audio or video). You should not watch the recording this year, it’s all happening live (advice).

If the video isn’t working you could also watch it on youtube. Or you can view just the slides (no audio or video). You should not watch the recording this year, it’s all happening live (advice).

If the slides are not working, or you prefer them full screen, please try this link.

The recording is available on stream and youtube.

Notes

What are moral intuitions?

On this course, a person’s intuitions are the claims they take to be true independently of whether those claims are justified inferentially. And a person’s moral intuitions are simply those of their intuitions that concern ethical matters.

Not everyone adopts this terminological stipulation. According to Sinnott-Armstrong, Young, & Cushman (2010, p. 256): ‘When we refer to moral intuitions, we mean strong, stable, immediate moral beliefs.’ For many purposes such differences are not critical. But note that philosophers sometimes the term ‘intuition’ use in ways that differ drastically. To illustrate, Bedke (2008) offers two ways of characterising what philosophers call intuitions:

’intuitions are understandings of self-evident propositions, where such understanding alone is sufficient for justification’ and ‘intuitions are sui generis seeming states [...] which are like [..] seemings based on sensory experience [...] in the way they justify’ (Bedke, 2008, p. 253)

Neither of these is a moral intuition for the purposes of this course.[1] (One could coherently maintain that moral intuitions exist in our sense while denying that there are any intuitions in Bedke’s sense.)

As well as moral intuitions, humans have linguistic intuitions and mathematical intuitions. Mathematical intuitions appear to be underpinned by relatively automatic processes which are independent of other mathematical abilities and may also be domain specific. It is possible that the same is true of moral intuitions. But note that we have not assumed this in our characterisation of them (this is a matter for discovery, not stipulation).

Why Are Moral Intuitions of Interest?

There are both philosophical and scientific reasons for interest in moral intuitions.

Philosophically, intuitions are key to a view in ethics called ‘Intuitionism’ whose key tennet is that ‘moral intutions [are] basic sources of evidence’ (Stratton-Lake, 2020, p. footnote~1). Although a minority view, moral intuitionism has recently gained some interesting proponents (Audi, 2015, for example).

Of wider interest, intuitions in philosophy are also essential for reflective equilibrium (Rawls, 1999). Many ethicists regard ‘the method of reflective equilibrium, or a process very similar to it, is the best or most fruitful method of moral inquiry [and] the one that seems most likely to lead to justified moral beliefs’ (McMahan, 2013, p. 111). Later in this course we will consider whether discoveries in moral psychology about intuitions are a good source of objections to the method of reflective equilibrium. This would be a major challenge to much contemporary ethics.

Scientifically, moral intuitions are interesting because of a fundamental feature of all cognition and action, namely speed–accuracy trade-offs. In general, the faster you must respond (or the less energy you can devote to responding), the less accurate you are likely to be (Heitz, 2014).[2] Since humans, like all animals, often stand to gain more from responding faster, and since they have historically had limited resources of energy, it is often advantageous for them to trade away accuracy in order to gain speed. Moral intuitions are important because they enable faster responses.

Our Question

In the first part of the course, we will focus on a single question:

How, if at all, do emotions influence moral intutions?

Ask a Question

Your question will normally be answered in the question session of the next lecture.

More information about asking questions.

Glossary

moral intuition : According to this lecturer, a person’s intuitions are the claims they take to be true independently of whether those claims are justified inferentially. And a person’s moral intuitions are simply those of their intuitions that concern ethical matters.
According to Sinnott-Armstrong et al. (2010, p. 256), moral intuitions are ‘strong, stable, immediate moral beliefs.’

References

Audi, R. (2015). Intuition and Its Place in Ethics. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 1(1), 57–77. http://0-dx.doi.org.pugwash.lib.warwick.ac.uk/10.1017/apa.2014.29
Bedke, M. S. (2008). Ethical Intuitions: What They Are, What They Are Not, and How They Justify. American Philosophical Quarterly, 45(3), 253–269.
Heitz, R. P. (2014). The speed-accuracy tradeoff: History, physiology, methodology, and behavior. Decision Neuroscience, 8, 150. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnins.2014.00150
Henmon, V. A. C. (1911). The relation of the time of a judgment to its accuracy. Psychological Review, 18(3), 186–201. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0074579
Link, S. W., & Tindall, A. D. (1971). Speed and accuracy in comparative judgments of line length. Perception & Psychophysics, 9(3), 284–288. https://doi.org/10.3758/BF03212649
McMahan, J. (2013). Moral Intuition. In The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory (pp. 103–120). Wiley. https://doi.org/10.1111/b.9780631201199.1999.00007.x
Rawls, J. (1999). A Theory of Justice (Revised edition). Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Young, L., & Cushman, F. (2010). Moral intuitions. In J. M. Doris, M. P. R. Group, & others (Eds.), The moral psychology handbook (pp. 246–272). Oxford: OUP.
Stratton-Lake, P. (2020). Intuitionism in Ethics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/intuitionism-ethics/

Endnotes

  1. As you would expect, other philosophers offer incompatible terminological stipulations about intuitions. See, for instance, Audi (2015, p. 65): ‘some intuitions have non-self-evident propositions as objects, for example, my intuition that I should protect the wandering toddler even with its apparent mother in view.’ ↩︎

  2. To illustrate, suppose you were required to judge which of two only very slightly different lines was longer. All other things being equal, making a faster judgement would involve being less accurate, and being more accurate would require making a slower judgement. (This idea is due to Henmon (1911), who has been influential although he didn't actually get to manipulate speed experimentally because of ‘a change of work’ (p. 195); see Link & Tindall (1971) for evidence.) ↩︎