Preview: Ethics vs Physics
In the domain of physics, almost no one today would advocate basing a theory on
intuitions. Historically, this involved lengthy (and bloody) struggle.
Thoughtful people can find themselves unable to give up intuitions even
in the face of overwhelming evidence. How are things different in the ethical
domain?
Notes
This is an optional section that sets the scene for a discussion of
dual-process theories of moral psychology by drawing a comparision
with physical cognition.
It is potentially confusing and not essential.
Very likely only a few people will find it useful.
Skip it.
What Is the Envisaged Conclusion
The envisaged conclusion (not yet argued for) is twofold:
-
Discoveries in moral psychology provide good reason not to
rely on not-justified-inferentially premises about particular scenarios
in arguing for (or against) ethical principles (see Greene contra Ethics (Railgun Remix)).
-
Discoveries in moral psychology could no more undermine, or support, ethical principles than
discoveries about physical cognition could undermine or support theories
in physics. (Unless the ethics-vs-linguistics comparison is right.)
Clarification
In the final part of the lecture recordings (last slide),
the discussion of scientific discoveries should be limited to
discoveries in moral psychology.
The claim under consideration is that discoveries in moral psychology
could no more undermine, or support, ethical principles than
discoveries about physical cognition could undermine or support theories
in physics.
Which comparison: Linguistic or Physical?
In this lecture, I am comparing ethical to physical cognition (and to
numerical cognition, and to mindreading). An alternative
would be to compare ethical to linguistic cognition.
If we do this,
we are likely to evaluate the main argument differently.
Each comparison has different advantages, although what their advantages
are may depend on your metaethical view (which is beyond the scope of this course).
Although I focus on the comparison with physical cognition, I attempt to indicate
which bits of the argument might be different if we relied on a comparison with linguistic
cognition in the notes. (But not in the slides or recordings.)
Historical Context for the Vertical Motion Example
Moletti (2000, p. 147),
who was Galileo’s predecessor in mathematics at Padua,
reports an early (1576 or earlier) experiment on the motion of objects launched vertically
in a dialogue:
‘PR. [...] Aristotle gave rise to doubts by saying that through one and the same
medium the speed of things that are moved in natural movement, being of the same
nature and shape, is as their powers. That is, if we were to let fall from the
top of a tall tower two balls, one of twenty pounds of lead and the other of one
pound, also of lead, that the movement of the larger would be twenty times
faster than that of the smaller.
‘AN. This seems sufficiently reasonable to me;
in fact, if I were asked I would grant it as a principle.
‘PR. You would be
mistaken; in fact, both arrive at one and the same time, even if the test were
done not once but many times. But what is more, a ball of wood, either larger or
smaller than one of lead, let fall from the same height at the same time as the
lead ball, would descend and touch the earth or ground at the same moment in
time.’
Glossary
David :
‘David is a great transplant surgeon. Five of his patients need new parts—one
needs a heart, the others need, respectively, liver, stomach, spleen, and
spinal cord—but all are of the same, relatively rare, blood-type. By chance,
David learns of a healthy specimen with that very blood-type. David can take
the healthy specimen's parts, killing him, and install them in his patients,
saving them. Or he can refrain from taking the healthy specimen's parts,
letting his patients die’
(Thomson, 1976, p. 206).
Edward :
‘Edward is the driver of a trolley, whose brakes have just failed. On the
track ahead of him are five people; the banks are so steep that they will not
be able to get off the track in time. The track has a spur leading off to
the right, and Edward can turn the trolley onto it. Unfortunately there is
one person on the right-hand track. Edward can turn the trolley, killing the
one; or he can refrain from turning the trolley, killing the five’
(Thomson, 1976, p. 206).
Frank :
‘Frank is a passenger on a trolley whose driver has just shouted that the
trolley's brakes have failed, and who then died of the shock. On the track
ahead are five people; the banks are so steep that they will not be able to get
off the track in time. The track has a spur leading off to the right, and
Frank can turn the trolley onto it. Unfortunately there is one person on the
right-hand track. Frank can turn the trolley, killing the one; or he can
refrain from turning the trolley, letting the five die’
(Thomson, 1976, p. 207).
intuition :
According to this lecturer, a person’s intuitions are the claims they take to be true
independently of whether those claims are justified inferentially. (Other sources may
define this term differently.)
not-justified-inferentially :
A claim (or premise, or principle) is not-justified-inferentially if it is not
justified in virtue of being inferred from some other claim (or premise, or principle).
Claims made on the basis of perception (That jumper is red, say) are typically
not-justified-inferentially.
Why not just say ‘noninferentially justified’? Because that can be read as implying that
the claim is justified, noninferentially. Whereas ‘not-justified-inferentially’ does not imply this.
Any claim which is not justified at all is thereby not-justified-inferentially.
unfamiliar problem :
An unfamiliar problem (or situation) is one ‘with which we have inadequate evolutionary, cultural, or personal experience’ (Greene, 2014, p. 714).
References
Descartes, R. (1998).
The world and other writings. (S. Gaukroger, Ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Freyd, J. J., & Finke, R. A. (1984). Representational momentum.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition,
10(1), 126–132.
https://doi.org/10.1037/0278-7393.10.1.126
Freyd, J. J., & Jones, K. T. (1994). Representational momentum for a spiral path.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition,
20(4), 968–976.
https://doi.org/10.1037/0278-7393.20.4.968
Greene, J. D. (2014). Beyond Point-and-Shoot Morality: Why Cognitive (Neuro)Science Matters for Ethics.
Ethics,
124(4), 695–726.
https://doi.org/10.1086/675875
Hubbard, T. L. (2010). Approaches to representational momentum: Theories and models. In R. Nijhawan & B. Khurana (Eds.),
Space and time in perception and action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hubbard, T. L. (2013). Launching, Entraining, and Representational Momentum: Evidence Consistent with an Impetus Heuristic in Perception of Causality.
Axiomathes,
23(4), 633–643.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-012-9186-z
Hubbard, T. L., Blessum, J. A., & Ruppel, S. E. (2001). Representational momentum and Michotte’s “launching effect” paradigm (1946/1963).
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition,
27(1), 294–301.
https://doi.org/10.1037/0278-7393.27.1.294
Kozhevnikov, M., & Hegarty, M. (2001). Impetus beliefs as default heuristics: Dissociation between explicit and implicit knowledge about motion.
Psychonomic Bulletin & Review,
8(3), 439–453.
https://doi.org/10.3758/BF03196179
McCloskey, M., Caramazza, A., & Green, B. (1980). Curvilinear Motion in the Absence of External Forces: Naive Beliefs about the Motion of Objects.
Science,
210(4474), 1139–1141.
https://doi.org/10.2307/1684819
Moletti, G. (2000).
The Unfinished Mechanics of Giuseppe Moletti: An Edition and English Translation of His Dialogue on Mechanics, 1576, translated by W. R. Laird. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Thomson, J. J. (1976). Killing, Letting Die, and The Trolley Problem.
The Monist,
59(2), 204–217.
https://doi.org/10.5840/monist197659224