Keyboard Shortcuts?

×
  • Next step
  • Previous step
  • Skip this slide
  • Previous slide
  • mShow slide thumbnails
  • nShow notes
  • hShow handout latex source
  • NShow talk notes latex source

Click here and press the right key for the next slide.

(This may not work on mobile or ipad. You can try using chrome or firefox, but even that may fail. Sorry.)

(If the slides don’t work, you can still use any direct links to recordings.)

also ...

Press the left key to go backwards (or swipe right)

Press n to toggle whether notes are shown (or add '?notes' to the url before the #)

Press m or double tap to slide thumbnails (menu)

Press ? at any time to show the keyboard shortcuts

 

Moral Intuitions and Heuristics: First Pass

Recall df. For the rest of today we will focus on just one moral ability, an ability to make intuitive judgements.
Moral psychology is the study of psychological aspects of ethical abilities.

Sinnott-Armstrong et al (2010), ‘Moral Intuitions’ in Doris et al (ed)

Our first topic will be moral intuitions

What are moral intutions?

Unreflective ethical / linguistic / mathematical judgements

Nothing special to say here ...

[1] He is a waffling fatberg of lies.

[2]* A waffling fatberg lies of he is.

Which box contains more dots?

Two projects -- everyday life vs philosophy

We are interested in moral inuitions in everyday life. They are an important part of our moral abilities.
You might also be interested in moral intuitions as a basis for evaluating philosophical approaches to reaching conclusions in ethics. This would be psychology of philosophy. My primary concern will not be with this, but with everyday unreflective ethical judgements.

What do adult humans compute that enables their unreflective judgements to track moral attributes (such as wrongness)?

To say that a state of you tracks an attribute is to say that whether you are in that state depends, perhaps within limits, on the presence of the attribute.
Clearly you can track an attribute without computing it. For example, your states of disgust track toxicity but are not typically a consequence of you computing that something is toxic: instead they compute smell.
Compare linguistic or mathematical judgements. Why is there any puzzle here? To see, we first need to think about something called inaccessibility.

1. Moral attributes are inaccessible.

‘We adopt the term accessibility to refer to the ease (or effort) with which particular mental contents come to mind’

Kahneman and Frederick, 2005 p. 271

\citep[p.~271]{kahneman:2005_model}

2. Unreflective ethical judgements are (often enough) fast.

3. Computing inaccessible attributes is slow.

Therefore:

4. Making unreflective ethical judgements does not involve computing moral attributes.

Do you understand the argument? And do you understand how it makes the question puzzling.
consider an analogy

What do adult humans compute that enables their unreflective judgements to track toxicity?

1. Toxicity is an inaccessible attribute.

2. Unreflective toxicity judgements are (often enough) fast.

3. Computing inaccessible attributes is slow.

Therefore:

4. Making unreflective toxicity judgements does not involve computing toxicity.

So how can we answer the question?

Inaccessible attribute:

- toxicity

Accessible attribute:

- how smelling it makes me feel

Substituting one attribute for another can enable you to give reasonable answers.

Heuristic: if smelling it makes you feel disgust, judge that it is toxic.

Why is this a heuristic? Because you’re built in such a way that, in a limited but useful range of cases, your feelings of disgust correlate with toxicity.
consider an analogy

What do adult humans compute that enables their unreflective judgements to track toxicity?

1. Toxicity is an inaccessible attribute.

2. Unreflective toxicity judgements are (often enough) fast.

3. Computing inaccessible attributes is slow.

Therefore:

4. Making unreflective toxicity judgements does not involve computing toxicity.

So all, or part, of the answer is disgust.

How is this relevant to the question about moral intuition?

I’m so glad you asked ...

What do adult humans compute that enables their unreflective judgements to track moral attributes (such as wrongness)?

1. Moral attributes are inaccessible.

2. Unreflective ethical judgements are (often enough) fast.

3. Computing inaccessible attributes is slow.

Therefore:

4. Making unreflective ethical judgements does not involve computing moral attributes.

Inaccessible attribute:

- rightness or wrongness (e.g.)

Accessible attribute:

Which accessible properties could be used in moral heuristics?

- how thinking about it makes me feel

the ‘affect heuristic’:

‘if thinking about an act [...] makes you feel bad [...], then judge that it is morally wrong’.

Sinnott-Armstrong et al, 2010

The ‘affect heuristic’: ‘if thinking about an act [...] makes you feel bad [...], then judge that it is morally wrong’ \citep{sinnott:2010_moral}.

What do adult humans compute that enables their unreflective judgements to track moral attributes (such as wrongness)?

1. Moral attributes are inaccessible.

2. Unreflective ethical judgements are (often enough) fast.

3. Computing inaccessible attributes is slow.

Therefore:

4. Making unreflective ethical judgements does not involve computing moral attributes.

They compute how thinking about it makes them feel.
Make sure you understand the question and you know what Sinnott-Armstrong et al (2010)’s answer is.

Sinnott-Armstrong et al (2010)’s claims about moral intuitions

Moral attributes are inaccessible.

‘Inaccessibility creates the need for a heuristic attribute’ (p. 257).

I.e. moral intuitions do not involve computing moral attributes.

Instead they involve using heuristics, i.e. computing accessible attributes which are correlated with moral attributes ...

... and, in particular, whether thinking about something makes you feel bad ('the affect heuristic').

Implications

Epistemic: ‘if moral intuitions result from heuristics, [... philosophers] must stop claiming direct insight into moral properties’

\citep[p.~268]{sinnott:2010_moral}.

Should we trust moral intuitions? ‘Just as non-moral heuristics lack reliability in unusual situations, so do moral intuitions’

\citep[p.~268]{sinnott:2010_moral}.

-- relevance: defending consequentialism

‘Critics often argue that consequentialism can’t be accurate, because it implies moral judgments that are counter-intuitive, such as that we are morally permitted to punish an innocent person in the well-known example where this is necessary to stop riots and prevent deaths. With the heuristic model in hand, consequentialists can respond that the target attribute is having the best consequences, and any intuitions to the contrary result from substituting a heuristic attribute.’
\citep[p.~269]{sinnott:2010_moral}.